Table of Contents
(Clicking on the links below will take you to those
parts of this article)
1. General Description
The term "Stoicism" derives from the Greek word "stoa,"
referring to a colonnade, such as those built outside or
inside temples, around dwelling-houses, gymnasia, and
market-places. They were also set up separately as
ornaments of the streets and open places. The simplest
form is that of a roofed colonnade, with a wall on one
side, which was often decorated with paintings. Thus in
the market-place at Athens the
stoa poikile
(Painted Colonnade) was decorated with Polygnotus's
representations of the destruction of Troy, the fight of
the Athenians with the Amazons, and the battles of
Marathon and Oenoe. Zeno of Citium taught in the
stoa poikile
in Athens, and his adherents accordingly obtained the
name of Stoics. Zeno was followed by Cleanthes, and then
by Chrysippus, as leaders of the school. The school
attracted many adherents, and flourished for centuries,
not only in Greece, but later in Rome, where the most
thoughtful writers, such as Marcus Aurelius, Seneca, and
Epictetus, counted themselves among its followers.
We know little for certain as to what share
particular Stoics, Zeno, Cleanthes, or Chrysippus, had
in the formation of the doctrines of the school, But
after Chryssipus the main lines of the doctrine were
complete. The stoic doctrine is divided into three
parts: logic, physics, and ethics. Stoicism is
essentially a system of ethics which, however, is guided
by a logic as theory of method, and rests upon physics
as foundation. Briefly, their notion of morality is
stern, involving a life in accordance with nature and
controlled by virtue. It is an ascetic system, teaching
perfect indifference (apathea) to everything
external, for nothing external could be either good or
evil. Hence to the Stoics both pain and pleasure,
poverty and riches, sickness and health, were supposed
to be equally unimportant.
2. Stoic Logic
Stoic logic is, in all essentials, the logic of
Aristotle. To this, however, they added a theory,
peculiar to themselves, of the origin of knowledge and
the criterion of truth. All knowledge, they said, enters
the mind through the senses. The mind is a blank slate,
upon which sense- impressions are inscribed. It may have
a certain activity of its own, but this activity is
confined exclusively to materials supplied by the
physical organs of sense. This theory stands, of course,
in sheer opposition to the idealism of Plato, for whom
the mind alone was the source of knowledge, the senses
being the sources of all illusion and error. The Stoics
denied the metaphysical reality of concepts. Concepts
are merely ideas in the mind, abstracted from
particulars, and have no reality outside consciousness.
Since all knowledge is a knowledge of sense-objects,
truth is simply the correspondence of our impressions to
things. How are we to know whether our ideas are correct
copies of things? How do we distinguish between reality
and imagination, dreams, or illusions? What is the
criterion of truth? It cannot lie in concepts, since
they are of our own making. Nothing is true save sense
impressions, and therefore the criterion of truth must
lie in sensation itself. It cannot be in thought, but
must be in feeling. Real objects, said the Stoics,
produce in us an intense feeling, or conviction, of
their reality. The strength and vividness of the image
distinguish these real perceptions from a dream or
fancy. Hence the sole criterion of truth is this
striking conviction, whereby the real forces itself upon
our consciousness, and will not be denied. There is,
thus, no universally grounded criterion of truth. It is
based, not on reason, but on feeling.
3. Stoic Physics
The fundamental proposition of the Stoic physics is
that "nothing incorporeal exists." This materialism
coheres with the sense-impression orientation of their
doctrine of knowledge. Plato placed knowledge in
thought, and reality, therefore, in the ideal form. The
Stoics, however, place knowledge in physical sensation,
and reality -- what is known by the senses -- is matter.
All things, they said, even the soul, even God himself,
are material and nothing more than material. This belief
they based upon two main considerations. Firstly, the
unity of the world demands it. The world is one, and
must issue from one principle. We must have a monism.
The idealism of Plato resolved itself into a futile
struggle involving a dualism between matter and thought.
Since the gulf cannot be bridged from the side of ideal
realm of the forms, we must take our stand on matter,
and reduce mind to it. Secondly, body and soul, God and
the world, are pairs which act and react upon one
another. The body, for example, produces thoughts (sense
impressions) in the soul, the soul produces movements in
the body. This would be impossible if both were not of
the same substance. The corporeal cannot act on the
incorporeal, nor the incorporeal on the corporeal. There
is no point of contact. Hence all must be equally
corporeal.
All things being material, what is the original kind
of matter, or stuff, out of which the world is made? The
Stoics turned to Heraclitus for an answer. Fire logos)
is the primordial kind of being, and all things are
composed of fire. With this materialism the Stoics
combined pantheism. The primal fire is God. God is
related to the world exactly as the soul to the body.
The human soul is likewise fire, and comes from the
divine fire. It permeates and penetrates the entire
body, and, in order that its interpenetration might be
regarded as complete, the Stoics denied the
impenetrability of matter. Just as the soul-fire
permeates the whole body, so God, the primal fire,
pervades the entire world.
But in spite of this materialism, the Stoics declared
that God is absolute reason. This is not a return to
idealism, and does not imply the incorporeality of God.
For reason, like all else, is material. It means simply
that the divine fire is a rational element. Since God is
reason, it follows that the world is governed by reason,
and this means two things. It means, firstly, that there
is purpose in the world, and therefore, order, harmony,
beauty, and design. Secondly, since reason is law as
opposed to the lawless, it means that universe is
subject to the absolute sway of law, is governed by the
rigorous necessity of cause and effect. Hence the
individual is not free. There can be no true freedom of
the will in a world governed by necessity. We may,
without harm, say that we choose to do this or that, and
that our acts are voluntary. But such phrases merely
mean that we assent to what we do. What we do is none
the less governed by causes, and therefore by necessity.
The world-process is
circular. God changes the fiery substance of himself
first into air, then water, then earth. So the world
arises. But it will be ended by a conflagration in which
all things will return into the primal fire. Thereafter,
at a pre-ordained time, God will again transmute himself
into a world. It follows from the law of necessity that
the course taken by this second, and every subsequent,
world, will be identical in every way with the course
taken by the first world. The process goes on for ever,
and nothing new ever happens. The history of each
successive world is the same as that of all the others
down to the minutest details.
The human soul is part of the divine fire, and
proceeds into humans from God. Hence it is a rational
soul, and this is a point of cardinal importance in
connection with the Stoic ethics. But the soul of each
individual does not come direct from God. The divine
fire was breathed into the first man, and thereafter
passed from parent to child in the act of procreation.
After death, all souls, according to some, but only the
souls of the good, according to others, continue in
individual existence until the general conflagration in
which they, and all else, return to God.
4. Stoic Ethics
The Stoic ethical teaching is based upon two
principles already developed in their physics; first,
that the universe is governed by absolute law, which
admits of no exceptions; and second, that the essential
nature of humans is reason. Both are summed up in the
famous Stoic maxim, "Live according to nature." For this
maxim has two aspects. It means, in the first place,
that men should conform themselves to nature in the
wider sense, that is, to the laws of the universe, and
secondly, that they should conform their actions to
nature in the narrower sense, to their own essential
nature, reason. These two expressions mean, for the
Stoics, the same thing. For the universe is governed not
only by law, but by the law of reason, and we, in
following our own rational nature, are ipso facto
conforming ourselves to the laws of the larger world. In
a sense, of course, there is no possibility of our
disobeying the laws of nature, for we, like all else in
the world, act of necessity. And it might be asked, what
is the use of exhorting a person to obey the laws of the
universe, when, as part of the great mechanism of the
world, we cannot by any possibility do anything else? It
is not to be supposed that a genuine solution of this
difficulty is to be found in Stoic philosophy. They
urged, however, that, though we will in any case do as
the necessity of the world compels us, it is given to us
alone, not merely to obey the law, but to assent to our
own obedience, to follow the law consciously and
deliberately, as only a rational being can.
Virtue, then, is the life according to reason.
Morality is simply rational action. It is the universal
reason which is to govern our lives, not the caprice and
self-will of the individual. The wise man consciously
subordinates his life to the life of the whole universe,
and recognizes himself as a cog in the great machine.
Now the definition of morality as the life according to
reason is not a principle peculiar to the Stoics. Both
Plato and Aristotle taught the same. In fact, it is the
basis of every ethic to found morality upon reason, and
not upon the particular foibles, feelings, or
intuitions, of the individual self. But what was
peculiar to the Stoics was the narrow and one- sided
interpretation which they gave to this principle.
Aristotle had taught that the essential nature of humans
is reason, and that morality consists in following this,
his essential nature. But he recognized that the
passions and appetites have their place in the human
organism. He did not demand their suppression, but
merely their control by reason. But the Stoics looked
upon the passions as essentially irrational, and
demanded their complete extirpation. They envisaged life
as a battle against the passions, in which the latter
had to be completely annihilated. Hence their ethical
views end in a rigorous and unbalanced asceticism.
Aristotle, in his broad and moderate way, though he
believed virtue alone to possess intrinsic value, yet
allowed to external goods and circumstances a place in
the scheme of life. The Stoics asserted that virtue
alone is good, vice alone evil, and that all else is
absolutely indifferent. Poverty, sickness, pain, and
death, are not evils. Riches, health, pleasure, and
life, are not goods. A person may commit suicide, for in
destroying his life he destroys nothing of value. Above
all, pleasure is not a good. One ought not to seek
pleasure. Virtue is the only happiness. And people must
be virtuous, not for the sake of pleasure, but for the
sake of duty. And since virtue alone is good, vice alone
evil, there followed the further paradox that all
virtues are equally good, and all vices equally evil.
There are no degrees.
Virtue is founded upon reason, and so upon knowledge.
Hence the importance of science, physics, logic, which
are valued not for themselves, but because they are the
foundations of morality. The prime virtues, and the root
of all other virtues, is therefore wisdom. The wise man
is synonymous with the good man. From the root-virtue,
wisdom, spring the four cardinal virtues: insight,
bravery, self-control, and justice. But since all
virtues have one root, those who possess wisdom possess
all virtue, and those who lack it lack all. A person is
either wholly virtuous, or wholly vicious. The world is
divided into wise and foolish people, the former
perfectly good, the latter absolutely evil. There is
nothing between the two. There is no such thing as a
gradual transition from one to the other. Conversion
must be instantaneous. the wise person is perfect, has
all happiness, freedom, riches, beauty. They alone are
the perfect kings, politicians, poets, prophets,
orators, critics, and physicians. The fool has all vice,
all misery, all ugliness, all poverty. And every person
is one or the other. Asked where such a wise person was
to be found, the Stoics pointed doubtfully at Socrates
and Diogenes the Cynic. The number of the wise, they
thought, is small, and is continually growing smaller.
The world, which they painted in the blackest colors as
a sea of vice and misery, grows steadily worse.
The similarities between Cynicism and Stoic ethics
are apparent. However, the Stoics modified and softened
the harsh outlines of Cynicism. To do this meant
inconsistency, though. It meant that they first laid
down harsh principles, and then proceeded to tone them
down, to explain them away, to admit exceptions. Such
inconsistency the stoics accepted with their habitual
cheerfulness. This process of toning down their first
harsh utterances took place mainly in three ways. First,
the modified their principle of the complete suppression
of the passions. Since this is impossible, and, if
possible, could only lead to immovable inactivity, they
admitted that the wise person might exhibit certain mild
and rational emotions. Thus, the roots of the passions
might be found in the wise person, though they would
never be allowed to grow. In the second place, they
modified their principle that all else, save virtue and
vice, is indifferent. Such a view is unreal, and out of
accord with life. Hence the stoics, with a masterly
disregard of consistency, stuck to the principle, and
yet declared that among things indifferent some are
preferable to others. If the wise person has the choice
between health and sickness, health is preferable.
Indifferent things were thus divided into three classes:
those to be preferred, those to be avoided, and those
which are absolutely indifferent.
In the third place, the stoics toned down the
principle that people are either wholly good, or wholly
evil. The famous heroes and politicians of history,
though fools, are yet polluted with the common vices of
humankind less than others. Moreover, what were the
Stoics to say about themselves? Were they wise men or
fools? They hesitated to claim perfection, to put
themselves on a level with Socrates and Diogenes. Yet
they could not bring themselves to admit that there was
no difference between themselves and the common herd.
They were "proficients," and, if not absolutely wise,
approximated to wisdom.
|