Quentin Smith has recently argued that (I) the
universe began to exist and (II) its beginning was uncaused. In support
of (II), he argues that (i) there is no reason to think that the
beginning was caused by God and (ii) it is unreasonable to think so. I
dispute both claims.
His case for (i) misconstrues the causal principle,
appeals to false analogies of ex nihilo creation, fails to show
how the origin of the universe ex nihilo is naturally
plausible, and reduces to triviality by construing causality as
predictability in principle. His case for (ii) ignores important
epistemological questions and fails to show either that vacuum
fluctuation models are empirically plausible or that they support his
second claim.
"The Caused Beginning of the Universe: a Response to
Quentin Smith." British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
44 (1993): 623-639.
Contents:
I.
Introduction
II. No Reason to Regard
the Theistic Hypothesis as True
III.
Unreasonable to Regard the Theistic Hypothesis as True
IV. Conclusion
Quentin Smith [1988] has recently argued that there is sufficient
evidence at present to warrant the conclusions that (i) the universe
probably began to exist and that (ii) it began to exist without being
caused to do so. While I am inclined to agree with (i),{1}
it seems to me that Smith has overstated the case for (ii).
As part of his argument for (ii), Smith takes on the task of
disproving what we may call the theistic hypothesis (TH), that the
beginning of the universe was caused by God. It is apparently Smith's
contention that the theist who believes in divine creatio ex nihilo
must fly in the face of the evidence in order to do so. But is this in
fact the case? As I read him, Smith's refutation of (TH) basically falls
into two halves: (i) there is no reason to regard (TH) as true, and (ii)
it is unreasonable to regard (TH) as true. Let us, therefore, examine
each half of his refutation in turn.
In order to show that there is no reason to think that God caused the
beginning of the universe, Smith attacks the universality of the causal
principle, variously construed. After arguing that ". . . it belongs
analytically to the concept of the cosmological singularity that it is
not the effect of prior physical events" and that "this effectively
rules out the idea that the singularity is an effect of some prior
natural process" (p. 48), Smith turns to the "more difficult question"
of whether the singularity or the Big Bang is the effect of a
supernatural cause. He presents the following argument (incorrectly
attributed to me) as a basis for inferring a supernatural cause of the
universe's origin:
- We have reason to believe that all events have a cause.
- The Big Bang is an event.
- Therefore, we have reason to believe that the Big Bang has a
cause.
While admitting that this argument does not violate singularity
theorems, since the cause is not conceived to be a spatio-temporal
object, Smith maintains that the argument fails because (1) is false.
Quoting me to the effect that "the causal proposition may be taken as an
empirical generalization enjoying the strongest support experience
affords," Smith rejoins that quantum mechanical considerations show that
the causal principle is limited in its application, so that a
probabilistic argument for a cause of the Big Bang cannot succeed. For
according to Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle, it is impossible to
predict precisely the conditions of the values of momentum or position
of some particle x at some time t2 on the
basis of our knowledge of the conditions of x at t1.
Since it sufficient to understand causality in terms of a law enabling
precise predictions of individual events to be deduced, it follows from
Heisenberg's Principle that there are uncaused events in this sense.{2}
Therefore, the causal proposition is not universally applicable and may
not apply to the Big Bang.
But what exactly is the causal proposition which is at issue here?
The proposition which I enunciated was not (1), as Smith alleges, but
rather
1.' Whatever begins to exist has a cause.
The motions of elementary particles described by statistical quantum
mechanical laws, even if uncaused, do not constitute an exception to
this principle. As Smith himself admits, these considerations "at most
tend to show that acausal laws govern the change of condition
of particles, such as the change of particle x's position from
q1 to q2. They state nothing
about the causality or acausality of absolute beginnings, of beginnings
of the existence of particles" (p. 50).
Smith seeks rectify this defect in his argument, however, by pointing
out that the Uncertainty relation also permits energy or particles
(notably virtual particles) to "spontaneously come into existence" for a
very brief time before vanishing again. It is therefore false that "all
beginnings of existence are caused" and, hence, ". . . the crucial step
in the argument to a supernatural cause of the Big Bang . . . is faulty"
(pp. 50-51).
But as a counterexample to (1'), Smith's use of such vacuum
fluctuations is highly misleading. For virtual particles do not
literally come into existence spontaneously out of nothing. Rather the
energy locked up in a vacuum fluctuates spontaneously in such a way as
to convert into evanescent particles that return almost immediately to
the vacuum. As John Barrow and Frank Tipler comment, ". . . the modern
picture of the quantum vacuum differs radically from the classical and
everyday meaning of a vacuum-- nothing. . . . The quantum vacuum (or
vacuua, as there can exist many) states . . . are defined simply as
local, or global, energy minima (V'(O)= O, V"(O)>O)" ([1986],
p. 440). The microstructure of the quantum vacuum is a sea of
continually forming and dissolving particles which borrow energy from
the vacuum for their brief existence. A quantum vacuum is thus far from
nothing, and vacuum fluctuations do not constitute an exception to the
principle that whatever begins to exist has a cause. It therefore seems
that Smith has failed to refute premiss (1').
Let us pursue Smith's argument further, however. He proceeds to argue
that there is no reason to think that the causal principle applies to
the Big Bang, whether one adopts a model based exclusively on the
General Theory of Relativity or whether one uses a model adjusted for
quantum effects during the Planck era. Consider on the one hand a model
in which quantum physics plays no role prior to 10-43 second
after the singularity. Since the classical notions of space and time and
all known laws of physics break down at the singularity, it is in
principle impossible to predict what will emerge from a singularity. If
we regard the Big Bang as the first physical state,{3}
then the particles that constitute that state must be regarded as being
randomly and spontaneously emitted from nothing at all. Smith states,
"This means, precisely put, that if the Big Bang is the first physical
state, then every configuration of particles that does constitute or
might have constituted this first state is as likely on a priori
grounds to constitute it as every other configuration of particles. In
[this] case, the constitution of the Big Bang1 is impossible
in principle to predict and thus is uncaused (for 'uncaused' minimally
means 'in principle unpredictable')" (p. 52). Moreover, since spacetime
curves cannot be extended beyond the singularity, it cannot have causal
antecedents.
On the other hand, consider a model in which quantum processes do
predominate near to the Big Bang. If the defender of the causal
principle maintains that the proposition
4. There are some uncaused beginnings of existence within
spacetime
is irrelevant to and thus cannot increase the probability of
5. The beginning of the existence of spacetime itself is
uncaused,
then Smith will respond that the same holds for the parallel argument
for a supernatural cause of four-dimensional spacetime. For the
proposition
6. All beginnings of existence within spacetime are
caused
would by the same token be irrelevant to and thus not increase the
probability of
7. The beginning of the existence of four- dimensional spacetime
is caused.
So whether one adopts a classical relativistic model or a quantum
model, there is no reason to postulate a cause, natural or supernatural,
of the Big Bang.
Is this a sound argument? It seems to me not. To pick up on a point
noted earlier, Smith's argument throughout his paper appears to be
infected with positivism, so that it is predicated upon a notion of
causality that is drastically inadequate. Smith assumes uncritically the
positivistic equation between predictability in principle and causation.
But this verificationist analysis is clearly untenable, as should be
obvious from the coherence of the position that quantum indeterminacy is
purely epistemic, there existing hidden variables which are in principle
unobservable, or even the more radical position of die-hard realists who
are prepared to abandon locality in order to preserve the hidden
variables. Clearly, then, to be "uncaused" does not mean, even
minimally, to be "in principle unpredictable."
This single point alone seems to me to vitiate Smith's entire
argument for his conclusion (ii) and against (TH) in particular. For now
we see that Smith's argument, even if successful, in no way proves that
the universe began to exist without a cause, but only that its beginning
to exist was unpredictable. What is ironic about this conclusion is that
it is one with which the theist is in whole-hearted agreement. For since
according to classical theism creation is a freely-willed act of God, it
follows necessarily that the beginning and structure of the universe
were in principle unpredictable even though it was caused by God. The
theist will therefore not only agree with Smith that "That there are
uncaused events in this sense follows from Heisenberg's
uncertainty principle" (p. 49), but even more insist that such uncaused
events are entailed by classical theism's doctrine of creation. He will
simply deny that this is the relevant sense when we are inquiring
whether the universe could have come into being uncaused out of nothing.
When we ask that question, we are asking whether the whole of being
could come out of non-being; and here a negative answer seems obvious.
Concerning this question, even genuine quantum indeterminacy affords no
evidence for an affirmative response. For if an event requires certain
physically necessary conditions in order to occur, but these conditions
are not jointly sufficient for its occurrence, and the event occurs,
then the event is in principle unpredictable, but it could hardly be
called uncaused in the relevant sense. In the case of quantum events,
there are any number of physically necessary conditions that must obtain
for such an event to occur, and yet these conditions are not jointly
sufficient for the occurrence of the event. (They are jointly sufficient
in the sense that they are all the conditions one needs for the event's
occurrence, but they are not sufficient in the sense that they guarantee
the occurrence of the event.) The appearance of a particle in a quantum
vacuum may thus be said to be spontaneous, but cannot be properly said
to be absolutely uncaused, since it has many physically necessary
conditions. To be uncaused in the relevant sense of an absolute
beginning, an existent must lack any non-logical necessary or sufficient
conditions whatsoever. Now at this juncture, someone might protest that
such a requirement is too stringent: "For how could anything
come into existence without any non-logical necessary or
sufficient conditions?" But this is my point exactly; if absolutely
nothing existed prior to the Big Bang--no matter, no energy, no space,
no time, no deity--, then it seems impossible that anything should begin
to exist.
As for Smith's two cases, then, in the case of the classical
relativistic theory, the fact that the universe originates in a naked
singularity only proves that we cannot predict what sort of
universe will emerge therefrom (and Smith does not claim otherwise), and
it leaves the coming-into-existence of the singularity itself
unexplained. If we interpret the singularity as a mathematical
idealization whose ontological counterpart is nothing, then it becomes
clear why the universe is unpredictable and why its unpredictability in
no way implies the possibility of its coming into being without a cause.{4}
As for Smith's consideration that a singularity is a point beyond which
spacetime curves cannot be extended, this only proves that the creation
event cannot have been brought about by any natural cause; but it does
not prove that a being which transcended space and time could not have
caused it.
As for the quantum case, the problem with the inference from (4) to
(5) is not that it moves from existents within the universe to the
universe as a whole, but rather that Smith's faulty concept of causation
makes the notion of "uncaused" equivocal. For some beginnings of
existence within spacetime are uncaused in the sense of being
spontaneous or unpredictable, but one cannot conclude that therefore
spacetime itself could come into being uncaused in the stronger sense of
arising from nothing in the utter absence of physically necessary and
sufficient conditions. But the inference from the necessity of causal
conditions for the origin of existents in spacetime to the necessity of
causal conditions for the origin of spacetime itself is not similarly
equivocal. Indeed, our conviction of the truth of the causal principle
is not based upon an inductive survey of existents in spacetime, but
rather upon the metaphysical intuition that something cannot come out of
nothing.{5} The
proper inference, therefore, is actually from "Whatever begins to exist
has a cause" and "The universe began to exist" to "The universe has a
cause," which is a logically impeccable inference based on universal
instantiation. It seems to me, therefore, that not only has Smith failed
to show that the Big Bang does not require a supernatural cause, but
that, on the contrary, we see from these considerations that if the
universe did originate from nothing, then that fact does point to a
supernatural cause of its origin.{6}
Hence, I conclude that Smith has failed to show that there is no
reason to regard (TH) as true.
If Smith is to prove his point (ii), in any case, he has to do much
more than show that there is no reason to adopt (TH). He has to show
that in light of the evidence, (TH) has now become unreasonable. Smith
believes the evidence for vacuum fluctuation models of the origin of the
universe is such as to render (TH) unreasonable. For it is physically
necessary for quantum effects to predominate near to the Big Bang, and
quantum mechanical models of the origin of the universe as or on the
analogy of a vacuum fluctuation provide the most probable account of the
origin of the universe out of nothing.
Now Smith's line of reasoning raises some intriguing epistemological
issues, to which, unfortunately, Smith gives no attention.{7}
Under what circumstances would it be irrational to believe in
supernatural creatio ex nihilo? Under what circumstances would
it be rational? When is a supernatural explanation preferable to a
naturalistic one and vice versa? Rather than seek to adjudicate
these questions, let us assume for the sake of argument that it would be
unreasonable, all things being equal, to posit a supernatural cause for
the origin of the universe when a plausible empirical explanation is
available or even likely to become available. Notice that in such a case
(TH) would not be falsified; it would simply be
unreasonable, all things being equal, to believe it. The question
is, then, whether vacuum fluctuation models of the origin of the
universe are or are likely to become plausible empirical explanations.
The answer to the question as to whether such models now provide
plausible empirical explanations for the universe's origin is, of
course, no, both because the theories are so problematic and
underdeveloped and because there is no empirical evidence in their
favor. Christopher Isham comments,
None of the schemes proposed so far are in any sense rigorous
theories. This stems partly from the lack of any proper unification
of general relativity and quantum theory. However, even setting this
aside, the extant proposals are incomplete; in particular it is by
no means clear that they do in fact lead to a unique quantum state.
Major conceptual problems arise when trying to apply quantum theory
to the universe as a whole. This problem is so severe that many
highly respectable theoretical physicists think the whole subject of
quantum cosmology is misconceived.
It follows from the above that theories of the quantum origin of
the universe are highly speculative and do not have anything like
the scientific status of, say, even the more exotic branches of
modern elementary particle physics (Isham [1992], sec. 1.5).
It is remarkable that Smith has so high a degree of confidence in
quantum fluctuation models that he thinks it unreasonable to believe in
(TH), for this is tantamount to saying that in light of these theories
it is no longer reasonable to hold to a Big Bang model involving a
singularity. But these theories are so inchoate, incomplete,
problematic, and poorly understood that they have not commended
themselves to most scientists as more plausible than traditional Big
Bang models. Of course, quantum effects will become important prior to
10-43 sec, but it is pure speculation that the
initial singularity will be averted.{8}
Smith's bold assertions on behalf of these models greatly overshoot
the modest, in some cases almost apologetic, claims made by the
proponents of the models themselves. Brout, Englert, and Gunzig, for
example, advised: "We present our work as a hypothesis; . . . For the
present all that can be said in favor of our hypothesis is that these
questions can be examined and on the basis of the answers be rejected or
found acceptable ([1978], pp. 78, 98). Atkatz and Pagels offered the
following justification: "While highly speculative, we believe this idea
is worth pursuing" ([1982], p. 2072). All that Vilenkin claimed on
behalf of his model was, "The advantages of the scenario presented here
are of aesthetic nature ([1982], p. 27). Other proponents of such models
claim no more than that their model is consistent with
observational data--and sometimes they do not even claim that much. In
fact, it is ironic that--apparently unbeknownst to Smith--several of the
original proponents of these models have, as we shall see, already
abandoned the vacuum fluctuation approach to cosmogeny as implausible
and are seeking elsewhere for explanations of the universe's origin.
Are these models then likely to become plausible empirical
explanations of the universe? Again it would be somewhat presumptuous to
give an affirmative answer to this question. Such models are provocative
and worth pursuing, but there is no reason to think that they are likely
to become plausible empirical explanations of the universe's origin.
Indeed, there is some reason to doubt that such models can ever become
plausible empirical explanations, since such models, by their
very nature, tend to posit events which are in principle inaccessible to
us, causally discontinuous with our universe or lying beyond event
horizons. According to Vilenkin, the only verifiable prediction made by
his model is that the universe must be closed--a prediction which
observational cosmology tends to falsify. Smith likes Gott's model
because it makes empirical predictions (Smith, [1986]). But so far as I
can see, his only prediction is that the universe is open, which is so
general as to be useless in serving as evidence for the model. None of
the proponents of such models has to my knowledge laid down conditions
which would verify his theory. J. P. Van der Weele concludes, "We will
never be able to determine which one of the possibilities is actually
true (if any), so all our ideas about the outer universe are doomed to
remain metaphysical speculations" ([1983], p. 36). At present, then,
such models are perhaps best viewed as naturalistic metaphysical
alternatives to (TH).
But even so construed, their superiority to theism is far from
obvious:
(1) Such models make the metaphysical presupposition that the
observed expansion of the universe is not, in fact, the expansion of the
Universe- as-a-whole, but merely the expansion of a restricted region of
it. Our expanding universe is contained in some sort of wider space
(whether a Minkowski space as in the Brout, Englert, Gunzig model or a
curved de Sitter space as in Gott's model) in which the quantum
fluctuations occur in the spacetime geometry which "pull" particles into
existence out of the energy locked up in empty space. Thus, throughout
this broader Universe-as-a-whole, which is considered to be a quantum
mechanical vacuum, fluctuations occur which blow up into distinct
material universes. But immediately the question arises, why, since all
the evidence we possess suggests that space is expanding, should we
suppose that it is merely our region of space (and regions like
it) that is expanding rather than all of space? This thesis
would appear to be in violation of the Copernican Principle, which holds
that we occupy no special place in the universe. This methodological
principle, which underlies all of modern astronomy and astrophysics,
would be violated because what we observe would not be typical of the
Universe at large. A violation of the principle in this case would
appear to be entirely gratuitous. Moreover, it is not just the postulate
of a different wider space that is required, but a good deal of
fine-tuning is necessary in order to get the space to spawn appropriate
universes. But there is no independent reason to think that such a
different wider space exists or, indeed, that a different wider space of
any sort at all exists. In this sense, the postulation of such a wider
space is an exercise in speculative metaphysics akin to the postulate of
theism--except that theism enjoys the advantage that there are at least
putative independent reasons for accepting the existence of God.
(2) Moreover, it is questionable whether the models at issue are
anything more than mathematical constructs lacking any physical
counterpart. For, as David Lindley [1987] points out, such models depend
on the use of certain mathematical "tricks" for their validity. For
example, quantities derived from the conformal factor most naturally
belong to the geometrical side of Einstein's equation, but by being put
on the other side of the equation they can be imagined to be part of the
stress energy tensor instead. This "rather arbitrary procedure" allows
one to think of the conformal factor as a physical field. But this seems
to be a clear case of unjustified ontologizing of a mathematical notion
into a physical entity. To make matters worse, proponents of such models
then propose the trick of coupling these conformal fields dynamically to
other more conventional physical components of the stress energy tensor,
such as the fields associated with particles similar to gauge bosons in
high energy physics. In this way the conformal field can be made to
generate regions of distorted geometry and a local density of particles.
But what reason or evidence is there to regard such a procedure as
anything more than mathematical legerdemain? As Barrow and Tipler point
out, "It remains to be seen whether any real physical meaning can be
associated with these results([1986], p. 441). Brout and Spindel, who
pioneered work on vacuum fluctuation models, now admit that the field
theoretical foundations of the production mechanisms as well as the
instability of the background space "are flimsy at best" ([1989], p.
216).
Nor does the comparison of the universe's origin to the spontaneous
production of a virtual particle serve to render these models plausibly
realistic. For if this comparison is meant to be reasoning by analogy,
then it seems extraordinarily weak, since the disanalogies between the
universe and a virtual particle are patent. If we are to believe with
Tryon [1973] that the universe literally is a virtual particle,
then this seems even more preposterous, since the universe has neither
the properties nor behavior of a virtual particle. One might ask, too,
why quantum fluctuations are not now spawning universes in our midst?
Why do vacuum fluctuations endure so fleetingly rather than grow into
mini- universes inside ours?
(3) Vacuum fluctuation models are incompatible with observational
cosmology. As Isham ([1990], p. 10; [1992], sec. 2) points out, there is
in such models simply no way in which the mathematics can select one
particular moment within the pre-existent, infinite, and homogeneous
time at which a fluctuation should occur which will spawn a universe.
Similarly, no way exists for specifying a certain point in space at
which such a creation event should occur. Rather vacuum fluctuation
theories tend to predict a creation event at every time t, or
more precisely, as quantum theories they predict a non-zero probability
of a creation event within any finite time interval, with an infinite
number of creation points distributed evenly throughout space. This
leads at once to an infinite number of creation events within the wider
spacetime. But then the fluctuation-formed universes would inevitably
collide with each other as they expand, which contradicts the findings
of observational cosmology, since we do not see such "worlds in
collision," to borrow a phrase.{9}
Gott [1982] attempts to avoid this difficulty by simply laying down
conditions where the fluctuations are allowed to occur in the wider
space. For any universe-spawning event E, there must not exist another
similar event E' in the past light cone of E. The volume of this region
which must be free of events like E is infinite. In order to prevent any
E' from occurring in this region, Gott stipulates that the probability
of randomly producing events like E per unit four-volume be
infinitesimal. Since de Sitter space is infinite, one can thus construct
a model of an infinite number of disjoint universes formed by
fluctuations. But not only is this scenario extraordinarily ad hoc,
but it does not seem even to avoid the difficulty.{10}
For given infinite past wider time, each of the infinite regions of the
de Sitter space will have spawned an open universe which will have
filled the volume of that region completely, so that all the bubble
universes will by now have collided or coalesced. About the only way to
avoid this consequence is to postulate an expansion of the background
space itself. But then we seem constrained to posit some origin of the
wider spacetime--and thus we are right back to where we started. Isham
regards this difficulty as "fairly lethal" to vacuum fluctuation models
and reports that "theories of this type have not found wide acceptance,"
commenting that their interest "lies mainly in some of the rather
general problems" that they raise ([1990], p. 10; [1988], p. 387).
(4) It is obvious from what has been said above that vacuum
fluctuation models have, in fact, nothing to do with the origination of
the universe ex nihilo. They posit metaphysical realities of
precise specifications in order to generate our universe. Some of them
are really more closely related to inflationary scenarios than to
cosmogeny. Interpreted cosmogenically, vacuum fluctuation models
constitute in the final analysis denials that the universe began to
exist, for it is only our observable segment of the universe that had a
beginning, not the Universe- as-a-whole. As Barrow and Tipler comment,
"It is, of course, somewhat inappropriate to call the origin of a bubble
Universe in a fluctuation of the vacuum 'creation ex nihilo,'
for the quantum mechanical vacuum state has a rich structure which
resides in a previously existing substratum of space-time, either
Minkowski or de Sitter space-time. Clearly, a true 'creation ex
nihilo' would be the spontaneous generation of
everything--space-time, the quantum mechanical vacuum, matter--at some
time in the past ([1986], p. 441). Smith admits that "A disadvantage of
. . . theories that postulate a background space from which the universe
fluctuates, is that they explain the existence of the universe but only
at the price of introducing another unexplained given, viz., the
background space" (p. 54). In that case, Smith has not only failed to
carry his point (ii), but (i) as well.
But Smith asserts that there are even more radical models of a
quantum origin of the universe that do not postulate the existence of a
wider space, but hold that the universe is the result of some sort of
quantum transition out of nothingness into being. For example, in the
Vilenkin model, the origin of the universe is understood on the analogy
of quantum tunneling, a process in which an elementary particle passes
through a barrier, though it lacks the energy to do so, because the
Uncertainty relation allows it to acquire spontaneously the energy for
the period of time necessary for it to pass through the barrier.
Vilenkin proposes that spacetime itself tunnels into existence out of
nothing, except that in this case there is no prior state of the
universe, but rather the tunneling itself is the first state that
exists.
Unfortunately, Smith seems to have misinterpreted in a literal way
Vilenkin's philosophically naive use of the term "nothing" for the
four-dimensional Euclidean space out of which our spacetime emerged.{11}
Be that as it may, if the quantum tunneling is supposed to be literally
from nothing, then such models seem to be conceptually flawed. For as
Thomas Aquinas saw (Summa contra gentiles 2.17), creation is
not properly any kind of a change or transition at all, since transition
implies the existence of an enduring subject, which is lacking in
creation. In a beginning to be out of nothing, there can be no talk
whatsoever of transition, quantum or otherwise. It is therefore
incoherent to characterize creation as a quantum transition out of
nothingness.
Even more fundamentally, however, what we are being asked to believe
is surely metaphysical nonsense. Though dressed up in the guise of a
scientific theory, the thesis at issue here is a philosophical one,
namely, can something come out of nothing? Concerning his own model,
even Vilenkin admits, "The concept of the universe being created from
nothing is a crazy one ([1982], p. 26). He tries to alleviate this
craziness by comparing it to particle pair creation and annihilation--an
analogy which we have seen to be altogether inadequate and in any case
irrelevant to the Vilenkin model as Smith interprets it, since he
supposedly lacks either the embedding quantum mechanical spacetime or
the Euclidean 4-space. The principle ex nihilo nihil fit seems
to me to be a sort of metaphysical first principle, one of the most
obvious truths we intuit when we reflect seriously. If the denial of
this principle is the alternative to a theistic metaphysic, then let
those who decry the irrationality of theism be henceforth forever
silent!
If this fourth criticism is on target, then vacuum fluctuation models
say nothing against divine creatio ex nihilo, for even if some
such model turns out to be correct, the theist will maintain that God
created the wider spacetime from which our material universe emerged. It
might be rejoined that there would then be no grounds for positing God
as the creator of the embedding spacetime, since there is no scientific
evidence that it began to exist. Not only is that not the case, as we
have seen, but divine creatio ex nihilo, as I have defended it
elsewhere, is grounded in revelation and philosophical argument, and the
scientific evidence merely serves as empirical confirmation of
that doctrine. The theist, after all, has no vested interest in
denominating the Big Bang as the moment of creation. He is convinced
that God created all of spacetime reality ex nihilo, and the
Big Bang model provides a powerful suggestion as to when that moment
was; on the other hand, if it can be demonstrated that our observable
universe originated in a broader spacetime, so be it--in that case it
was this wider reality that was the immediate object of God's creation.
But unless the conceptual difficulties in such models can be overcome
and some empirical evidence for them is forthcoming, the theist will
probably apply Ockham's Razor and be content to regard the Big Bang as
the creation event.
(5) I earlier alluded to the fact that vacuum fluctuation models have
been abandoned as plausible accounts of the origin of the universe by
some of their principal expositors and to that extent are already
somewhat dated. Brout, Englert, and Spindel of the Free University of
Brussels, where much of the theoretical work on these models was done,
have, for example, moved beyond such models and have criticized the
attempt of some of their colleagues to refurbish the old, untenable
models (Brout and Spindel, [1989], pp. 215-16). They now contend that an
explanation of the origin of the universe "must await the yet-to-come
quantum theory of gravity." The quantum gravity model that seems to have
fired the imagination of many current theorists is the model of Hartle-Hawking
[1983] based on the assigning of a wave function to the universe.
Unfortunately, models of this sort confront acute philosophical
difficulties concerning the metaphysics of time.{12}
(i) Such models presuppose a geometrodynamical interpretation of
spacetime that suppresses objective temporal becoming in favor of a
Parmenidean, static construal of the dynamics of spacetime in terms of
positions on a leaf of history in superspace.{13}
Already this reduction of spacetime to a leaf of history in superspace
has completed the Parmenidean reinterpretation of the dynamics of time
along static lines, for the arena of geometrodynamics is not a
super-spacetime, but a superspace alone. But the introduction
of quantum theory into geometrodynamics--a move essential to wave
functional models of the origin of our 4-geometry--not only makes
spacetime ontologically derivative from superspace, but, far more,
actually expunges spacetime altogether, for quantum theory makes it
impossible to distinguish sharply between 3-geometries on a leaf of
history in superspace and those not on it, due to indeterminacy. Misner,
Thorne, and Wheeler state,
That object which is central to all of classical general
relativity, the four-dimensional spacetime geometry, simply does not
exist, except in a classical approximation.
. . . one has to forego that view of nature in which every event,
past, present, or future, occupies its pre-ordained position in a
grand catalog called 'space-time' . . . . There is no spacetime,
there is no time, there is no before, there is no after ([1973], pp.
1182-3).
(ii) Such models convert time into a spatial dimension by employing
imaginary numbers for the time coordinate prior to the Planck time.{14}
Construed realistically, this is just bad metaphysics. Space is a
dimension ordered by a relation of betweeness: for three
successive points x, y, and z on a spatial line, y
is between x and z. But time is ordered in addition by
a unique relation of earlier/later than: for two successive
moments t1 and t2
in time, t1 is earlier than t2,
and t2 is later than t1.
While spatial points are not ordered by any such relation, this relation
is essential to the nature of time; as Schlesinger points out, "The
relations 'before' and 'after' have generally been acknowledged as being
the most fundamental temporal relations, which means that time deprived
of these relations would cease to be time" ([1975], p. 171). It is thus
metaphysically impossible for time to be a dimension of space. Moreover,
as an ardent A-theorist who holds to the objective reality of tensed
facts, Smith regards moments of time as essentially possessing the
shifting properties or relations of presentness, pastness, and futurity.
Nothing even remotely like these A-determinations characterizes units of
space. Thus, Smith must agree that the notion of imaginary time, a sort
of spatialized time, is metaphysically impossible. Now perhaps quantum
gravitational models could be interpreted as holding, not that time in
the earliest stages of the universe is imaginary, but rather that as one
goes back in time one arrives at a regime in which time (gradually)
ceases to exist and is replaced by a fourth spatial dimension. But such
an interpretation is still metaphysically problematic. First, it would
imply that the earliest segment of the universe was timeless, which
contradicts the claim that this era existed before real time
began. As Smith himself demands, "If the four-dimensional space does not
possess a real time value, how can it stand in relation to the four-
dimensional spacetime of being earlier than it? If the four-dimensional
space is not in a real (Lorentzian) time, then it is not really earlier
than, later than, or simultaneous with the four-dimensional spacetime
manifold" ([1993], p. 318). Secondly, it seems impossible for this
Euclidean 4-space to "hook up," so to speak, with the real temporal
history of the universe. Once the first moment of time had elapsed, that
moment was in the past. But the timeless, Euclidean 4-space cannot be in
the past, since it is timeless. Thus, there never could have been a time
when it was "hooked up" to our temporal universe, since then it would
have been present, which is impossible. Hawking seems to realize the
impossibility of having two stages of the universe, one timeless and the
other temporal, and so he is driven to the Parmenidean position that our
universe's existing in real time is just an illusion ([1988], p. 139)!
But as Smith points out, such an interpretation is "preposterous . . .
at least observationally, since it is perfectly obvious that the
universe in which we exist lapses in real rather than imaginary time"
([1993], p. 319).
In order to avert the metaphysical difficulties of the Parmenidean
construal of the nature of time inherent in such theories, Smith is
forced to interpret quantum gravitational models' employment of
geometrodynamics and imaginary time instrumentally rather than
realistically and to take the beginning of the universe out of nothing
to occur at the first moment of real time ([1993], p. 321). But then we
are right back to the metaphysical absurdity of something's coming into
being uncaused out of nothing. Smith interprets Hawking's model as
establishing a certain probability for the first three-dimensional slice
of spacetime to appear uncaused out of nothing. But this is a mistake,
for the probability of finding any three-dimensional cross-section of
spacetime in such quantum models is only relative to some other
cross-section given as one's point of departure (Isham [1988], pp.
395-400). As Isham emphasizes, quantum models hope to give a
description of the earliest state of the universe, but do not
purport to explain it: "Note that the one question which even a
very ambitious creation theorist cannot (or, perhaps, should not)
address is 'Why is there anything at all?' That is strictly a job for
philosophers and theologians!" (Isham [1992], p. 4)
It seems to me, therefore, that even if we concede that it would be
unreasonable, all things being equal, to posit divine creatio ex
nihilo when a plausible, empirical hypothesis for the origin of the
universe is available or even likely to become available, Smith has
failed to show that (TH) is unreasonable. Moreover, for the theist, it
is not the case that all things are equal in this matter, for he has
independent reasons (from philosophy and revelation) for accepting
creatio ex nihilo apart from the scientific evidence. If these
reasons are sound, then he would be rational in accepting (TH) even if a
plausible, empirical account of the world's origin were available--which
at present it most certainly is not--though he might not in such a case
have a clue as to the moment of creation.
In conclusion, then, I think it is clear that Smith has failed to
carry the second prong of his argument, namely, that the universe began
to exist without being caused to do so. In his attempt to show that
there is no good reason to accept the theistic hypothesis, he
misconstrued the causal proposition at issue, appealed to false
analogies of ex nihilo creation, contradicted himself in
holding the singularity to be the source of the universe, failed to show
why the origin of the universe ex nihilo is reasonable on
models adjusted or unadjusted for quantum effects, and, most
importantly, trivialized his whole argument through the reduction of
causation to predictability in principle, thus making his conclusion an
actual entailment of theism. Nor has he been any more successful in
proving that the theistic hypothesis is unreasonable in light of the
evidence. For he ignores the important epistemological questions
concerning the circumstances under which it would be rational to accept
divine creatio ex nihilo; he has failed to show that vacuum
fluctuation models are or are likely to become plausible, empirical
explanations of the universe's origin; on the contrary, such models are
probably best regarded as naturalistic metaphysical alternatives to the
theistic hypothesis, but as such are fraught with conceptual
difficulties; and, most importantly, such models, on pain of ontological
absurdity, do not in fact support Smith's (ii), so that they do not
render unreasonable the hypothesis that God created the universe,
including whatever wider spatio-temporal realms of reality might be
imagined to exist.
Endnotes
{1}
See Craig [1979], pp. 65-140; Smith has offered refutations of some of
my philosophical arguments against an infinite temporal regress of
events in Craig and Smith [1993], pp. 77-91; his objections do not,
however, seem decisive, as I try to show in Craig and Smith [1993], pp.
92-107.
{2}
Notice that Smith's claim that such events are uncaused is predicated on
the very dubious equivalence between "unpredictability in principle" and
"uncausedness," an equivalence which I shall criticize in the text. If
all that quantum indeterminism amounts to is "uncausedness" in the sense
of "unpredictability in principle," then the demonstration that quantum
events are uncaused in this sense fails to confute the causal
proposition at issue in the first premiss of the kalam
argument, unpredictability being an epistemic affair which may or may
not result from an ontological indeterminism. For clearly, it would be
entirely consistent to maintain determinism on the quantum level even if
we could not, even in principle, predict precisely such events.
In this paper, however, I shall not assume some controversial "hidden
variables" view, but shall for the sake of argument go beyond Smith and
assume that indeterminism does hold on the quantum level. For discussion
see Shimony [1978], pp. 3-17; Aspect and Grangier [1986], pp. 1- 15; and
Bhave [1986], pp. 467-75.
{3}
Smith's own view that the universe began to exist at to
and that the state of affairs existing at to in 0,
1, or 2 dimensions is the source of the universe contradicts his claim
that the universe began to exist uncaused, for on his view the universe
did not come from nothing but is causally connected to the singularity,
whose existence remains unexplained. Smith rejects Newton-Smith's demand
for a cause of the singularity. Therefore, his argument for (ii) fails.
{4} I
cannot refrain from referring again to Anscombe [1973-74], p. 150. As
she points out, we can form various pictures in our minds and give them
appropriate titles, e.g. "Superforce Emerging from the
Singularity" or "Gravitons Emerging from the Singularity," but our
ability to do that says absolutely nothing about whether it is
ontologically possible for something to come into being uncaused out of
nothing.
{5} My
defense of the causal proposition as an "empirical generalization
enjoying the strongest support experience affords" cited by Smith was in
its original context a last ditch defense of the principle designed to
appeal to the hard-headed empiricist who resists the metaphysical
intuition that properly grounds our conviction of the principle (Craig
[1979], pp. 141-48). It does seem to me that only an aversion to the
theism implied by the principle in the present context would lead the
empiricist to think that the denial of the principle is more plausible
than the principle itself.
{6}
Such a cause would have to be uncaused, eternal, changeless, immaterial,
and spaceless; it would, as I have argued elsewhere, also have to be
personal and therefore merits the appellation "God" (Craig [1979], pp.
149-53; Craig [1991]).
{7}
See, however, Morris [1987], pp. 151-60, for some initial and
interesting analysis of these issues.
{8}
See also the interesting discussion by Barrow and Tipler [1988], pp.
31-34, in which they explain that since we have no tested theory of
quantum gravitation to supersede General Relativity nor any
observational evidence for the existence of matter fields which violate
the strong or weak energy conditions, the initial cosmological
singularity has not been eliminated. In fact, they point out that the
finiteness of the action in Friedman models is due to the cosmological
singularities. "Thus in general there is a trade-off between space-time
singularities: a singularity in the action is avoided only at the price
of a singularity in curvature invariants, and vice versa. In
cosmology some sort of singularity seems inevitable" (pp. 32-33).
{9}
See the similar objection urged against the quantum tunneling model of
Atkatz and Pagels by M. Munitz, Cosmic Understanding
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), p.136, who observes, "For
if the actual closed universe arose by a process of quantum tunneling
from a prior stable initial state, then the universe in its pre-creation
state could not remain indefinitely long in that state, if indeed it is
unstable with respect to quantum tunneling." Atkatz and Pagels have
admittedly no answer to the question of how the universe got into its
pre-creation state. Cf. the analogous reasoning of Davies [1978], p.
336.
{10}
See a similar objection urged by Barrow and Tipler [1986], pp. 602-07,
who point out that although Gott's model posits a causal structure of
the background space consisting of infinitely many non-intersecting,
open bubble universes, there must be such a bubble universe in the past
light cone of any event p, given a constant probability of
bubble formation in the de Sitter space. Notice that because Gott's
bubbles are potentially infinite in their expansion, so long as the
bubbles are formed after p they will not intersect; the walls
of each bubble reach spacelike infinity at an infinite time in the
future. But since "the volume of an open bubble becomes infinite in an
infinite time," then given an infinite past prior to p, it
follows that the past light cone of any p will already contain
an open bubble universe that has already expanded to infinity. So also
Isham [1988], p. 387.
{11}
See Isham [1992], sec. 5.4.
{12}
For more on this see Craig [1990], pp. 473-91.
{13}
For discussion, see Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler [1973], pp. 1180-95. Cf.
"There is no such thing as spacetime in the real world of quantum
physics. . . . superspace leaves us space but not spacetime and
therefore not time. With time gone the very ideas of 'before' and
'after' also lose their meaning" (Wheeler [1973], p. 227; see also
Wheeler [1980], pp. 346-50 and the therein cited literature.
{14}
Isham remarks, "Although these schemes differ in their details they all
agree on the idea that space and time emerge in some way from a purely
quantum mechanical region which can be described in some respects as if
it were a classical, imaginary-time four-space" ([1992], sec. 5.6).
REFERENCES
Anscombe, G.E.M. (1973-74), "'Whatever Has a Beginning of Existence
Must Have a Cause': Hume's Argument Exposed," Analysis
34:145-51.
Aspect, A. and Grangier, P. (1986), "Experiments on
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen type correlations with pairs of visible
photons," in R. Penrose and C.J. Isham (eds.), Quantum Concepts in
Space and Time. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 1-15.
Atkatz, D. and Pagels, H. (1982), "Origin of the Universe as a
Quantum Tunneling Event," Physical Review D 25:2065-73.
Barrow, J. and Tipler, F.J. (1986), The Cosmological Anthropic
Principle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
________. (1988), "Action principles in nature," Nature
331:31- 34.
Bhave, S. (1986), "Separable Hidden Variables Theory to Explain
Einstein- Podolsky-Rosen Paradox," British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science 37:467-75.
Brout, R., Englert, F., and Gunzig, E. (1978), "The Creation of the
Universe as a Quantum Phenomenon," Annals of Physics
115:78-106.
Brout R. and Spindel, Ph. (1989), "Black Holes Dispute," Nature
337:215-16.
Craig, Wm. (1979), The Kalam Cosmological Argument,
Library of Philosophy and Religion. London: Macmillan.
________. (1990), "'What Place, then, for a Creator?': Hawking on God
and Creation," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
41:473-91.
________. (1991), "The Kalam Cosmological Argument and the
Hypothesis of a Quiescent Universe," Faith and Philosophy
8:492- 503.
Craig, Wm. and Smith, Q. (1993), Theism, Atheism, and Big Bang
Cosmology. Oxford: Clarendon.
Davies, P.C.W. (1978), "Cosmic Heresy?" Nature 273:336.
Gott III, J.R. (1982), "Creation of Open Universes from de Sitter
Space," Nature 295:304-07.
Gunzig, E., Géhéniau, J., and Prigogine, I. (1987), "Entropy and
Cosmology," Nature 330:621-24.
Hartle, J. and Hawking, S. (1983), "Wave function of the Universe,"
Physical Review D 28:2960-75.
Hawking, S. (1988), A Brief History of Time. London: Bantam.
Isham, C. (1988), "Creation of the Universe as a Quantum Process," in
R. Russell, W. Stoeger, and G. Coyne (eds.), Physics, Philosophy,
and Theology: a Common Quest for Understanding. Vatican
City State: Vatican Observatory, pp. 375-408.
________. (1990), "Space, Time and Quantum Cosmology, " paper
presented at the conference "God, Time and Modern Physics," March, 1990,
sponsored by the Science and Religion Forum.
________. (1992), "Quantum Theories of the Creation of the Universe,"
unpublished paper, a preliminary version of which appears in V. Brümmer
(ed.), Interpreting the Universe as Creation, The Netherlands:
Pharos, 1991.
Lindley, D. (1987), "Cosmology from Nothing," Nature
330:603-4.
Misner, C., Thorne, K.S., and Wheeler, J.A. (1973),Gravitation.
San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.
Morris, T. (1987), "Creation ex Nihilo: Some
Considerations," in Anselmian Explanations. Notre Dame, Ind.:
University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 151-60.
Munitz, M. (1986), Cosmic Understanding. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Schlesinger, G. (1975), "The Similarities between Space and Time,"
Mind 84:161-76.
Shimony, A. (1978), "Metaphysical Problems in the Foundations of
Quantum Mechanics," International Philosophical Quarterly
18:3-17.
Smith, Q. (1986), "World Ensemble Explanations," Pacific
Philosophical Quarterly 67:73-86.
________. (1988), "The Uncaused Beginning of the Universe,"
Philosophy of Science 55:39-57.
Tryon, E. (1973), "Is the Universe a Vacuum Fluctuation?" Nature
246:396-97.
Van der Weele, J. (1983), "The Inflationary Universe," unpublished
thesis, University of Utrecht.
Vilenkin, A. (1982), "Creation of Universes from Nothing"
Physical Letters B 117:25-28.
Wheeler, J.A. (1973), "From Relativity to Mutability," in J. Mehra
(ed.), The Physicist's Conception of Nature. Dordrecht: D.
Reidel, pp. 202-47.
________. (1980), "Beyond the Black Hole," in Harry Wolf (ed.),
Some Strangeness in the Proportion. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley
Publishing Co., pp. 341-75.