Moral
education is becoming an increasingly popular topic in the fields of
psychology and education. Media reports of increased violent juvenile
crime, teen pregnancy, and suicide have caused many to declare a moral
crisis in our nation. While not all of these social concerns are moral
in nature, and most have complex origins, there is a growing trend
towards linking the solutions to these and related social problems to
the teaching of moral and social values in our public schools. However,
considerations of the role schools can and should play in the moral
development of youth are themselves the subject of controversy. All too
often debate on this topic is reduced to posturing reflecting personal
views rather than informed opinion. Fortunately, systematic research and
scholarship on moral development has been going on for most of this
century, and educators wishing to attend to issues of moral development
and education may make use of what has been learned through that work.
The following overview provides an introduction to the main perspectives
guiding current work on moral development and education. Readers
interested in gaining an in-depth and up-to-date understanding of
research and scholarship in the field may do so by returning to this web
site each month and selecting
Featured
Articles.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Piaget's Theory
Jean
Piaget is among the first psychologists whose work remains directly
relevant to contemporary theories of moral development. In his early
writing, he focused specifically on the moral lives of children,
studying the way children play games in order to learn more about
children's beliefs about right and wrong(1932/65). According to Piaget,
all development emerges from action; that is to say, individuals
construct and reconstruct their knowledge of the world as a result of
interactions with the environment. Based on his observations of
children's application of rules when playing, Piaget determined that
morality, too, can be considered a developmental process. For example,
Ben, a ten year old studied by Piaget, provided the following critique
of a rule made-up by a child playing marbles: "it isn't a rule! It's a
wrong rule because it's outside of the rules. A fair rule is one that is
in the game". Ben believed in the absolute and intrinsic truth of the
rules, characteristic of early moral reasoning. In contrast, Vua, aged
thirteen, illustrates an understanding of the reasoning behind the
application of rules, characteristic of later moral thinking. When asked
to consider the fairness of a made-up rule compared to a traditional
rule, Vua replied "It is just as fair because the marbles are far
apart"(making the game equally difficult).
In addition to examining
children's understanding of rules about games, Piaget interviewed
children regarding acts such as stealing and lying. When asked what a
lie is, younger children consistently answered that they are "naughty
words". When asked why they should not lie, younger children could
rarely explain beyond the forbidden nature of the act: "because it is a
naughty word". However, older children were able to explain "because it
isn't right", and "it wasn't true". Even older children indicated an
awareness of intention as relevant to the meaning of an act: "A lie is
when you deceive someone else. To make a mistake is when you make a
mistake". From his observations, Piaget concluded that children begin in
a "heteronomous" stage of moral reasoning, characterized by a strict
adherence to rules and duties, and obedience to authority.
This heteronomy results
from two factors. The first factor is the young child's cognitive
structure. According to Piaget, the thinking of young children is
characterized by egocentrism. That is to say that young children are
unable to simultaneously take into account their own view of things with
the perspective of someone else. This egocentrism leads children to
project their own thoughts and wishes onto others. It is also associated
with the uni-directional view of rules and power associated with
heteronomous moral thought, and various forms of "moral realism." Moral
realism is associated with "objective responsibility", which is valuing
the letter of the law above the purpose of the law. This is why young
children are more concerned about the outcomes of actions rather than
the intentions of the person doing the act. Moral realism is also
associated with the young child's belief in "immanent justice." This is
the expectation that punishments automatically follow acts of
wrong-doing. One of the most famous cases of such childhood thinking was
that of the young boy who believed that his hitting a power pole with
his baseball bat caused a major power blackout in the New York city
area.
The second major
contributor to heteronomous moral thinking in young children, is their
relative social relationship with adults. In the natural authority
relationship between adults and children, power is handed down from
above. The relative powerlessness of young children, coupled with
childhood egocentrism feeds into a heteronomous moral orientation.
However, through
interactions with other children in which the group seeks a to play
together in a way all find fair, children find this strict heteronomous
adherence to rules sometimes problematic. As children consider these
situations, they develop towards an "autonomous" stage of moral
reasoning, characterized by the ability to consider rules critically,
and selectively apply these rules based on a goal of mutual respect and
cooperation. The ability to act from a sense of reciprocity and mutual
respect is associated with a shift in the child's cognitive structure
from egocentrism to perspective taking. Coordinating one's own
perspective with that of others means that what is right needs to be
based on solutions that meet the requirements of fair reciprocity. Thus,
Piaget viewed moral development as the result of interpersonal
interactions through which individuals work out resolutions which all
deem fair. Paradoxically, this autonomous view of morality as fairness
is more compelling and leads to more consistent behavior than the
heteronomous orientation held by younger children.
Piaget concluded from this
work that schools should emphasize cooperative decision-making and
problem solving, nurturing moral development by requiring students to
work out common rules based on fairness. This is a direct rejection of
sociologists Emile Durkheim's view of proper moral education
(1925/1961). Durkheim, similar to Piaget, believed that morality
resulted from social interaction or immersion in a group. However,
Durkheim believed moral development was a natural result of attachment
to the group, an attachment which manifests itself in a respect for the
symbols, rules, and authority of that group. Piaget rejected this belief
that children simply learn and internalize the norms for a group; he
believed individuals define morality individually through their
struggles to arrive at fair solutions. Given this view, Piaget suggested
that a classroom teacher perform a difficult task: the educator must
provide students with opportunities for personal discovery through
problem solving, rather than indoctrinating students with norms.
An excellent contemporary
adaptation of Piaget's theory for moral development of young children
may be found in DeVries, R. & Zan, B. (1994). "Moral Children:
Constructing a Constructivist Atmosphere in Early Education." New York:
Teachers College Press. You may preview some portions of that book
within the
Classroom
Practices segment of this web site. DeVries and Zan go beyond
Piaget's original work to include that of more recent theorists
including Lawrence Kohlberg whose theory will be described next.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Kohlberg's Theory of
Moral Development and Education
Moral
Development
Lawrence
Kohlberg (1969) modified and elaborated Piaget's work, and laid the
groundwork for the current debate within psychology on moral
development. Consistent with Piaget, he proposed that children form ways
of thinking through their experiences which include understandings of
moral concepts such as justice, rights, equality and human welfare.
Kohlberg followed the development of moral judgment beyond the ages
studied by Piaget, and determined that the process of attaining moral
maturity took longer and was more gradual than Piaget had proposed.
On the basis of his
research, Kohlberg identified six stages of moral reasoning grouped into
three major levels. Each level represented a fundamental shift in the
social-moral perspective of the individual. At the first level, the
preconventional level, a person's moral judgments are characterized by a
concrete, individual perspective. Within this level, a Stage 1
heteronomous orientation focuses on avoiding breaking rules that are
backed by punishment, obedience for its own sake and avoiding the
physical consequences of an action to persons and property. As in
Piaget's framework, the reasoning of Stage 1 is characterized by
ego-centrism and the inability to consider the perspectives of others.
At Stage 2 there is the early emergence of moral reciprocity. The Stage
2 orientation focuses on the instrumental, pragmatic value of an action.
Reciprocity is of the form, "you scratch my back and I'll scratch
yours." The Golden Rule becomes, "If someone hits you, you hit them
back." At Stage 2 one follows the rules only when it is to someone's
immediate interests. What is right is what's fair in the sense of an
equal exchange, a deal, an agreement. At Stage 2 there is an
understanding that everybody has his(her) own interest to pursue and
these conflict, so that right is relative (in the concrete individualist
sense).
Individuals at the
conventional level of reasoning, however, have a basic understanding of
conventional morality, and reason with an understanding that norms and
conventions are necessary to uphold society. They tend to be
self-identified with these rules, and uphold them consistently, viewing
morality as acting in accordance with what society defines as right.
Within this level, individuals at Stage 3 are aware of shared feelings,
agreements, and expectations which take primacy over individual
interests. Persons at Stage 3 define what is right in terms of what is
expected by people close to one's self, and in terms of the stereotypic
roles that define being good - e.g., a good brother, mother, teacher.
Being good means keeping mutual relationships, such as trust, loyalty,
respect, and gratitude. The perspective is that of the local community
or family. There is not as yet a consideration of the generalized social
system. Stage 4 marks the shift from defining what is right in terms of
local norms and role expectations to defining right in terms of the laws
and norms established by the larger social system. This is the "member
of society" perspective in which one is moral by fulfilling the actual
duties defining one's social responsibilities. One must obey the law
except in extreme cases in which the law comes into conflict with other
prescribed social duties. Obeying the law is seen as necessary in order
to maintain the system of laws which protect everyone.
Finally, the post
conventional level is characterized by reasoning based on principles,
using a "prior to society" perspective. These individuals reason based
on the principles which underlie rules and norms, but reject a uniform
application of a rule or norm. While two stages have been presented
within the theory, only one, Stage 5, has received substantial empirical
support. Stage 6 remains as a theoretical endpoint which rationally
follows from the preceding 5 stages. In essence this last level of moral
judgment entails reasoning rooted in the ethical fairness principles
from which moral laws would be devised. Laws are evaluated in terms of
their coherence with basic principles of fairness rather than upheld
simply on the basis of their place within an existing social order.
Thus, there is an understanding that elements of morality such as regard
for life and human welfare transcend particular cultures and societies
and are to be upheld irrespective of other conventions or normative
obligations. These stages (1-5) have been empirically supported by
findings from longitudinal and cross-cultural research (Power et al.,
1989).
Moral Education
Kohlberg
used these findings to reject traditional character education practices.
These approaches are premised in the idea that virtues and vices are the
basis to moral behavior, or that moral character is comprised of a "bag
of virtues", such as honesty, kindness, patience, strength, etc.
According to the traditional approach, teachers are to teach these
virtues through example and direct communication of convictions, by
giving students an opportunity to practice these virtues, and by
rewarding their expression. However, critiques of the traditional
approach find flaws inherent in this model. This approach provides no
guiding principle for defining what virtues are worthy of espousal, and
wrongly assumes a community consensus on what are considered "positive
values". In fact, teachers often end up arbitrarily imposing certain
values depending upon their societal, cultural, and personal beliefs. In
order to address this issue of ethical relativity, some have adopted the
values-clarification approach to moral education. This teaching practice
is based on the assumption that there are no single, correct answers to
ethical dilemmas, but that there is value in holding clear views and
acting accordingly. In addition, there is a value of toleration of
divergent views. It follows, then, that the teacher's role is one of
discussion moderator, with the goal of teaching merely that people hold
different values; the teacher does attempt to present her views as the
"right" views.
Kohlberg rejected the
focus on values and virtues, not only due to the lack of consensus on
what virtues are to be taught, but also because of the complex nature of
practicing such virtues. For example, people often make different
decisions yet hold the same basic moral values. Kohlberg believed a
better approach to affecting moral behavior should focus on stages of
moral development. These stages are critical, as they consider the way a
person organizes their understanding of virtues, rules, and norms, and
integrates these into a moral choice (Power, Higgins, & Kohlberg, 1989).
In addition, he rejected the relativist view point in favor of the view
that certain principles of justice and fairness represent the pinnacle
of moral maturity, as he found that these basic moral principles are
found in different cultures and subcultures around the world (Kohlberg &
Turiel, 1971).
The goal of moral
education, it then follows, is to encourage individuals to develop to
the next stage of moral reasoning. Initial educational efforts employing
Kohlberg's theory were grounded in basic Piagetian assumptions of
cognitive development. Development, in this model, is not merely the
result of gaining more knowledge, but rather consists of a sequence of
qualitative changes in the way an individual thinks. Within any stage of
development, thought is organized according to the constraints of that
stage. An individual then interacts with the environment according to
their basic understandings of the environment. However, the child will
at some point encounter information which does not fit into their world
view, forcing the child to adjust their view to accommodate this new
information. This process is called equilibration, and it is through
equilibration that development occurs. Early moral development
approaches to education, therefore, sought to force students to ponder
contradiction inherent to their present level of moral reasoning.
The most common tool for
doing this was to present a "moral dilemma" (see
Classroom
Practices) and require students to determine and justify what course
the actor in the dilemma should take. Through discussion, students
should then be forced to face the contradictions present in any course
of action not based on principles of justice or fairness.
While Kohlberg appreciated
the importance and value of such moral dilemma discussions, he held from
very early on that moral education required more than individual
reflection, but also needed to include experiences for students to
operate as moral agents within a community. In this regard, Kohlberg
reconciled some of the differences in orientation that existed between
the theories of moral growth held by Piaget and Durkheim. In order to
provide students with an optimal context within which to grow morally,
Kohlberg and his colleagues developed the "just community" schools
approach towards promoting moral development (Power, Higgins, &
Kohlberg, 1989). The basic premise of these schools is to enhance
students' moral development by offering them the chance to participate
in a democratic community. Here, democracy refers to more than simply
casting a vote. It entails full participation of community members in
arriving at consensual rather than "majority rules" decision-making. One
primary feature of these schools is their relatively small size (often
they are actually schools within schools), aimed at providing the
students with a sense of belonging to a group which is responsive to
individual needs. The central institution of these schools is a
community meeting in which issues related to life and discipline in the
schools are discussed and democratically decided, with an equal value
placed on the voices of students and teachers. An underlying goal of
these meetings is to establish collective norms which express fairness
for all members of the community. It is believed that by placing the
responsibility of determining and enforcing rules on students, they will
take prosocial behavior more seriously. At the same time, this approach
stems from the cognitive-developmentalist view that discussion of moral
dilemmas can stimulate moral development.
However, this is not to
say that just community school simply leaves students to their own
devices; teachers play a crucial leadership role in these discussions,
promoting rules and norms which have a concern for justice and
community, and ultimately enforcing the rules. This role is not an easy
one, as teachers must listen closely and understand a student's
reasoning, in order to help the student to the next level of reasoning.
This requires a delicate balance between letting the students make
decisions, and advocating in a way which shows them the limits in their
reasoning. A primary advantage to the Just Community approach is its
effectiveness in affecting students actions, not just their reasoning.
Students are, in effect, expected to "practice what they preach", by
following the rules determined in community meetings.
The most comprehensive and
authoritative source for work on Kohlberg's approach to moral education
is to be found in : Power, F. C., Higgins, A., & Kohlberg, L. (1989).
"Lawrence Kohlberg's Approach to Moral Education." New York: Columbia
University Press.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Domain Theory:
Distinguishing Morality and Convention
In
the early 1970s, longitudinal studies conducted by the Kohlberg research
group began to reveal anomalies in the stage sequence. Researchers
committed to the basic Kohlberg framework attempted to resolve those
anomalies through adjustments in the stage descriptions (see the Power,
Higgins, & Kohlberg, 1989 reference for an account of those changes).
Other theorists, however, found that a comprehensive resolution to the
anomalous data required substantial adjustments in the theory itself.
One of the most productive lines of research to come out of that period
has been the domain theory advanced by Elliot Turiel and his colleagues.
Within domain theory a
distinction is drawn between the child's developing concepts of
morality, and other domains of social knowledge, such as social
convention. According to domain theory, the child's concepts of morality
and social convention emerge out of the child's attempts to account for
qualitatively differing forms of social experience associated with these
two classes of social events. Actions within the moral domain, such as
unprovoked hitting of someone, have intrinsic effects (i.e., the harm
that is caused) on the welfare of another person. Such intrinsic effects
occur irregardless of the nature of social rules that may or may not be
in place regarding the action. Because of this, the core features of
moral cognition are centered around considerations of the effects which
actions have upon the well-being of persons. Morality is structured by
concepts of harm, welfare, and fairness.
In contrast, actions that
are matters of social convention have no intrinsic interpersonal
consequences. For example, there is nothing intrinsic to the forms of
address we employ that makes calling a college teacher "professor"
better or worse than calling the person Mr. or Ms., or simply using
their given names. What makes one form of address better than another is
the existence of socially agreed upon rules. These conventions, while
arbitrary in the sense that they have no intrinsic status, are
nonetheless important to the smooth functioning of any social group.
Conventions provide a way for members of the group to coordinate their
social exchanges through a set of agreed upon and predictable modes of
conduct. Concepts of convention then, are structured by the child's
understandings of social organization.
These hypothesized
distinctions have been sustained through studies over the past 20 years.
These studies have included interviews with children, adolescents and
adults; observations of child-child and adult-child social interactions;
cross-cultural studies; and longitudinal studies examining the changes
in children's thinking as they grow older. An example of the distinction
between morality and convention is given in the following excerpt from
an interview with a four-year-old girl regarding her perceptions of
spontaneously occurring transgressions at her preschool.
MORAL ISSUE: Did
you see what happened? Yes. They were playing and John hit him too hard.
Is that something you are supposed to do or not supposed to do? Not so
hard to hurt. Is there a rule about that? Yes. What is the rule? You're
not to hit hard. What if there were no rule about hitting hard, would it
be all right to do then? No. Why not? Because he could get hurt and
start to cry.
CONVENTIONAL ISSUE:
Did you see what just happened? Yes. They were noisy. Is that something
you are supposed to or not supposed to do? Not do. Is there a rule about
that? Yes. We have to be quiet. What if there were no rule, would it be
all right to do then? Yes. Why? Because there is no rule.
Morality and convention,
then, are distinct, parallel developmental frameworks, rather than a
single system as thought of by Kohlberg. However, because all social
events, including moral ones, take place within the context of the
larger society, a person's reasoning about the right course of action in
any given social situation may require the person to access and
coordinate their understandings from more than one of these two social
cognitive frameworks. For, example, whether people line up to buy movie
theater tickets is largely a matter of social convention. Anyone who has
traveled outside of Northern Europe or North America can attest to the
fact that lining up is not a shared social norm across cultures. Within
the United States or England, for example, lining up is the conventional
way in which turn-taking is established. The act of turn-taking has a
moral consequence. It establishes a mechanism for sharing - an aspect of
distributive justice. The act of breaking in line within the American or
British context is more than merely a violation of convention. It is a
violation of a basic set of rules that people hold to maintain fairness.
How people coordinate the possible interactions that may arise between
issues of morality and convention is a function of several factors
including: the salience of the features of the act (what seems most
important - the moral or conventional elements); and the developmental
level of the person (adolescents for example view conventions as
unimportant and arbitrary norms established by adult authority).
It was Turiel's insight to
recognize that what Kohlberg's theory attempts to account for within a
single developmental framework is in fact the set of age-related efforts
people make at different points in development to coordinate their
social normative understandings from several different domains. Thus,
domain theory posits a great deal more inconsistency in the judgments of
individuals across contexts, and allows for a great deal more likelihood
of morally (fairness and welfare) based decisions from younger and less
developed people than would be expected from within the traditional
Kohlberg paradigm.
Current work from within
domain theory has sought to explore how the child's concepts of moral
and conventional regulation relate to their developing understandings of
personal prerogative and privacy. This work is exploring how children
develop their concepts of autonomy and its relation to social authority.
This has led to a fruitful series of studies of adolescent-parent
conflict with important implications for ways in which parents may
contribute to the healthy development of youth (Smetana, 1996). This
work is also being extended into studies of how adolescents perceive the
authority of teachers and school rules. Moral and Social Values
Education The implications of domain theory for values education are
several. First, the identification of a domain of moral cognition that
is tied to the inherent features of human social interaction means that
moral education may be grounded in universal concerns for fairness and
human welfare, and is not limited to the particular conventions or norms
of a given community or school district. By focusing on those universal
features of human moral understanding, public schools may engage in
fostering children's morality without being accused of promoting a
particular religion, and without undercutting the basic moral core of
all major religious systems.
Second, educational
research from within domain theory has resulted in a set of
recommendations for what is termed "domain appropriate" values
education. This approach entails the teacher's analysis and
identification of the moral or conventional nature of social values
issues to be employed in values lessons. Such an analysis contributes to
the likelihood that the issues discussed are concordant with the domain
of the values dimension they are intended to affect. A discussion of
dress codes, for example, would constitute a poor basis for moral
discussion, since mode of dress is primarily a matter of convention.
Likewise, consideration of whether it is right to steal to help a person
in need, would be a poor issue with which to generate a lesson intended
to foster students' understandings of social conventions. A related
function of the teacher would be to focus student activity (verbal or
written) on the underlying features concordant with the domain of the
issue. Thus, students dealing with a moral issue would be directed to
focus on the underlying justice or human welfare considerations of the
episode. With respect to conventions, the focus of student activity
would be on the role of social expectations and the social
organizational functions of such social norms.
On the basis of this kind
of analysis teachers are also better enabled to lead students through
consideration of more complex issues which contain elements from more
than one domain. By being aware of the developmental changes that occur
in students' comprehension of the role of social convention, and related
changes in students understanding of what it means to be fair or
considerate of the welfare of others, teachers are able to frame
consideration of complex social issues in ways that will maximize the
ability of students to comprehend and act upon the moral and social
meaning of particular courses of action.
The best sources for
discussion of domain appropriate education, along with guidelines and
examples for how teachers may select materials from existing school
curricula from which to generate lessons and practices which will foster
students' development within both the moral and conventional domains may
be found in: Nucci, L. & Weber, E. (1991) "The domain approach to values
education: From theory to practice" In W. Kurtines & J. Gewirtz (Eds.)
"Handbook of Moral Behavior and Development (Volume 3: Applications)pp.
251 - 266). and also in: Nucci, L. (1989) "Challenging Conventional
Wisdom About Morality: The Domain Approach to Values Education." In L.
Nucci (Ed.) "Moral Development and Character Education: A Dialogue"
Berkeley: McCutchan.
Examples of such materials
and practices will be provided in coming months on the
Classroom
Practices segment of this web site.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Carol Gilligan and the
Morality of Care
A
second major critique of Kohlberg's work was put forth by Carol
Gilligan, in her popular book, "In a Different Voice: Psychological
Theory and Women's Development" (1982). She suggested that Kohlberg's
theories were biased against women, as only males were used in his
studies. By listening to women's experiences, Gilligan offered that a
morality of care can serve in the place of the morality of justice and
rights espoused by Kohlberg. In her view, the morality of caring and
responsibility is premised in nonviolence, while the morality of justice
and rights is based on equality. Another way to look at these
differences is to view these two moralities as providing two distinct
injunctions - the injunction not to treat others unfairly (justice) and
the injunction not to turn away from someone in need (care). She
presents these moralities as distinct, although potentially connected.
In her initial work,
Gilligan emphasized the gender differences thought to be associated with
these two orientations. The morality of care emphasizes
interconnectedness and presumably emerges to a greater degree in girls
owing to their early connection in identity formation with their
mothers. The morality of justice, on the other hand, is said to emerge
within the context of coordinating the interactions of autonomous
individuals. A moral orientation based on justice was proposed as more
prevalent among boys because their attachment relations with the mother,
and subsequent masculine identity formation entailed that boys separate
from that relationship and individuate from the mother. For boys, this
separation also heightens their awareness of the difference in power
relations between themselves and the adult, and hence engenders an
intense set of concerns over inequalities. Girls, however, because of
their continued attachment to their mothers, are not as keenly aware of
such inequalities, and are, hence, less concerned with fairness as an
issue. Further research has suggested, however, that moral reasoning
does not follow the distinct gender lines which Gilligan originally
reported. The preponderance of evidence is that both males and females
reason based on justice and care. While this gender debate is unsettled,
Gilligan's work has contributed to an increased awareness that care is
an integral component of moral reasoning.
Educational approaches
based on Gilligan's work have emphasized efforts to foster empathy and
care responses in students. Perhaps the most comprehensive treatment of
these issues may be found in Nel Noddings book, "The challenge to care
in schools" New York: Teachers College Press, 1992.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Conclusion
This
segment was designed to provide an overview of the major developmental
theories currently influencing research on moral education. To remain
current with new information and approaches in this very active field
you should check this web site on a regular basis for
Featured
Articles. To learn about available books in the field check
Books of
Interest. For persons wanting to learn more about traditional
character education please check
Related Web
Sites.
This overview was prepared
by Mary Elizabeth Murray, Department of Psychology, University if
Illinois at Chicago. Comments or inquiries for further information
should be directed to Professor Larry
Nucci, University of Illinois at Chicago.
back to top |
Printer Friendly Version
Piaget's Theory | Kohlberg's
Theory | Domain Theory
Carol Gilligan |
Conclusion | Selected References
Selected References
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a
different voice: Psychological theory and women's development. Harvard
University Press: Cambridge.
Kohlberg, L. & Turiel, E.
(1971). Moral development and moral education. In G. Lesser, ed.
Psychology and educational practice. Scott Foresman.
Piaget, J. (1965). The
moral judgment of the child. The Free Press: New York. Power, F. C.,
Higgins, A., & Kohlberg, L. (1989). "Lawrence Kohlberg's Approach to
Moral Education." New York: Columbia University Press.
Smetana, J. G. (1996, in
press). "Parenting and the development of social knowledge
reconceptualized: A social domain analysis." To appear in J.E. Grusec &
L. Kuczynski (Eds.), Handbook of parenting and the transmission of
values. New York: Wiley.
Turiel, E. (1983). "The
Development of Social Knowledge: Morality & Convention." New York:
Cambridge University Press. |